Summary
Note: Though Behe is not a creationist, this response to criticism is provided here for the benefit of those considering the questionable nature of today’s mainstream evolutionary paradigm. |
|
n this essay I reply to what I consider to be
the most important claim made by any critic of intelligent design:
that direct experimental evidence has shown that evolution can
indeed generate irreducibly complex biochemical systems. As I will
show below, the claim is false.
Briefly, in his book
Finding Darwin’s God (Harper Collins, 1999) Kenneth Miller
quite rightly says that a “true acid test” of Darwinism is to see if
it could regenerate an irreducibly complex system that was knocked
out using the tools of molecular biology. He then discusses work
from the laboratory of Barry Hall of the University of Rochester on
the lac operon of the bacterium E. coli. Miller
strongly implies that natural selection pieced together the whole
pathway in Hall’s experiments, but in fact it only replaced one
component (and even then it could only replace the component with a
spare near-copy of the original component). When two or more
components were deleted, or when the bacterium was cultured in the
absence of an artificial chemical (called IPTG), no viable bacteria
could be recovered. Just as irreducible complexity would predict,
when several steps must be taken at once, natural selection is a
poor way to proceed.
Since Miller calls this work the “acid
test,” that of course means that other examples he discusses in his
book are not “acid tests” they are at best indirect arguments. The
more indirect the argument, the easier for Darwinists to overlook or
conceal difficulties.
“A True Acid Test”
Brown University cell biologist Kenneth Miller has written a
book recently defending Darwinism from a variety of critics,
including me. In a chapter devoted to rebutting Darwin’s Black
Box, he marshals an array of examples which, he asserts, tell
against claims of irreducible complexity. However, for all of his
counterexamples I either disagree that he is dealing with
irreducibly complex systems, disagree that he is focusing on the
irreducibly complex aspects of a system, or disagree that his brief
scenarios successfully answer the challenge of irreducible
complexity (for an example, see my critique on this website of his
blood clotting scenario). In this section I focus on his most
serious claim—that an experiment has shown natural selection can
construct an irreducibly complex system.
Professor Miller
correctly states that “a true acid test” of the ability of Darwinism
to deal with irreducible complexity would be to “[use] the tools of
molecular genetics to wipe out an existing multipart system and then
see if evolution can come to the rescue with a system to replace
it.” (Miller 1999, 145) Therefore the most important and novel part
of Miller’s rebuttal is his claim that experimental work in a
bacterial system has actually succeeded in producing an irreducibly
complex system by natural selection. In a section entitled “Parts is
Parts,” in which he discusses the careful work over the past
quarter-century of Barry Hall of the University of Rochester on the
experimental evolution of a lactose-utilizing system in E.
coli, Miller excitedly remarks:
Think for a moment—if
we were to happen upon the interlocking biochemical complexity of
the reevolved lactose system, wouldn’t we be impressed by the
intelligence of its design? Lactose triggers a regulatory sequence
that switches on the synthesis of an enzyme that then metabolizes
lactose itself. The products of that successful lactose metabolism
then activate the gene for the lac permease, which ensures a
steady supply of lactose entering the cell. Irreducible complexity.
What good would the permease be without the galactosidase? . . . No
good, of course. By the very same logic applied by Michael Behe to
other systems, therefore, we could conclude that the system had been
designed. Except we know that it was not designed. We know it
evolved because we watched it happen right in the laboratory!
(Miller 1999, 146)
I will show this picture is grossly exaggerated.
Here is a brief description of how the
lac operon functions. The lac operon of E. coli
contains genes coding for several proteins which are involved in
metabolism of the disaccharide lactose. One protein of the
lac operon, called a permease, imports lactose through the
otherwise-impermeable cell membrane. Another protein is an enzyme
called ß-galactosidase, which can hydrolyze the disaccharide to its
two constituent monosaccharides, galactose and glucose, which the
cell can then process further. Because lactose is rarely available
in the environment, the bacterial cell switches off synthesis of the
permease and ß-galactosidase to conserve energy until lactose is
available. The switch is controlled by another protein called a
repressor, whose gene is located next to the operon. Ordinarily the
repressor binds to the lac operon, shutting it off by
physically interfering with expression of the operon. In the
presence of the natural “inducer” allolactose (a by-product of
lac ß-galactosidase activity) or the artificial chemical
inducer isopropylthiogalactoside (IPTG), however, the repressor
binds to the inducer and releases the operon, allowing the
lac operon enzymes to be synthesized by the cell.
When I first read this section of Miller’s book I was quite
impressed by the prospect that actual experiments—not theoretical,
“just-so” stories—had produced a genuine, non-trivial
counterexample to irreducible complexity. After going back to read
Professor Hall’s publications, however, I found that the situation
was considerably different. Not only were Hall’s results not what I
expected based on Miller’s description, in fact they fit most
naturally within a framework of irreducible complexity and
intelligent design. The same work that Miller points to as an
example of Darwinian prowess I would cite as showing the limits of
Darwinism and the need for design.
Adaptive Mutation
So what did Barry Hall actually do? To study
bacterial evolution in the laboratory, in the mid 1970s Hall
produced a strain of E. coli in which the gene for just the
ß-galactosidase of the lac operon was deleted. He later
wrote:
All of the other functions for lactose metabolism,
including lactose permease and the pathways for metabolism of
glucose and galactose, the products of lactose hydrolysis, remain
intact, thus re-acquisition of lactose utilization requires only the
evolution of a new ß-galactosidase function. (Hall 1999)
Thus, contrary to Miller’s own criterion for “a true acid
test,” a multipart system was not “wiped out”—only one component of
a multipart system was deleted.
Without ß-galactosidase,
Hall’s cells could not grow when cultured on a medium containing
only lactose as a carbon source. However, when grown on a plate that
also included alternative, useable nutrients, bacterial colonies
could be established. When the other nutrients were exhausted the
colonies stopped growing. However, Hall noticed that after several
days to several weeks, hyphae grew on some of the colonies. Upon
isolating cells from the hyphae, Hall saw that they frequently had
two mutations, one of which was in a gene for a protein he called
“evolved ß-galactosidase,” (“ebg”) which allowed it to
metabolize lactose efficiently. (Despite considerable efforts by
Hall to determine it, the natural function of ebg remains
unknown) (Hall 1999). The ebg gene is located in another
operon, distant from the lac operon, and is under the control
of its own repressor protein. The second mutation Hall found was
always in the gene for the ebg repressor protein, which
caused the repressor to bind lactose with sufficient strength to
de-repress the ebg operon.
The fact that there were
two separate mutations in different genes—neither of which by
itself allowed cell growth (Hall 1982a)—startled Hall, who knew
that the odds against the mutations appearing randomly and
independently were prohibitive (Hall 1982b). Hall’s results and
similar results from other laboratories led to research in the area
dubbed “adaptive mutations.” (Cairns 1998; Foster 1999; Hall 1998;
McFadden and Al Khalili 1999; Shapiro 1997) As Hall later wrote,
Adaptive mutations are mutations that occur in nondividing
or slowly dividing cells during prolonged nonlethal selection, and
that appear to be specific to the challenge of the selection in the
sense that the only mutations that arise are those that provide a
growth advantage to the cell. The issue of the specificity has been
controversial because it violates our most basic assumptions about
the randomness of mutations with respect to their effect on the
cell. (Hall 1997)
The mechanism(s) of adaptive mutation are
currently unknown. While they are being sorted out, it is misleading
to cite results of processes which “violate our most basic
assumptions about the randomness of mutations” to argue for
Darwinian evolution, as Miller does.
A Nearly-Identical Active Site
The nature of adaptive
mutation aside, a strong reason to consider the
lac/ebg results quite modest is that the ebg
proteins—both the repressor and ß-galactosidase—are homologous to
the E. coli lac proteins and overlap the proteins in
activity. Both of the unmutated ebg proteins already bind
lactose. Binding of lactose even to the unmutated ebg
repressor induces a 100-fold increase in synthesis of the ebg
operon. (Hall 1982a) Even the unmutated ebg ß-galactosidase
can hydrolyze lactose at a level of about 10% that of a “Class II”
mutant ß-galactosidase that supports cell growth. (Hall 1999) These
activities are not sufficient to permit growth of E. coli on
lactose, but they already are present. The mutations reported by
Hall simply enhance pre-existing activities of the proteins. In a
recent paper (Hall 1999) Professor Hall pointed out that both the
lac and ebg ß-galactosidase enzymes are part of a
family of highly-conserved ß-galactosidases, identical at 13 of 15
active site amino acid residues, which apparently diverged by gene
duplication more than two billion years ago. The two mutations in
ebg ß-galactosidase that increase its ability to hydrolyze
lactose change two nonidentical residues back to those of other
ß-galactosidases in ebg’s phylogenetic class, so that their
active sites are identical. Thus—before any experiments were
done—the ebg active site was already a near-duplicate of
other ß-galactosidases, and only became more active by becoming a
complete duplicate. Significantly, by phylogenetic analysis Hall
concluded that those two mutations are the only ones in E.
coli that confer the ability to hydrolyze lactose.
The
phylogenetic evidence indicates that either Asp-92 and Cys/Trp-977
are the only acceptable amino acids at those positions, or that all
of the single base substitutions that might be on the pathway to
other amino acid replacements at those sites are so deleterious that
they constitute a deep selective valley that has not been traversed
in the 2 billion years since those proteins diverged from a common
ancestor. (Hall 1999)
Such results hardly support
extravagant claims for the creativeness of Darwinian processes.
Caveats Unmentioned
A critical caveat not
mentioned by Kenneth Miller is that the mutants that were initially
isolated would be unable to use lactose in the wild—they required
the artificial inducer IPTG to be present in the growth medium. The
reason is that a permease is required to bring lactose into the
cell. However, ebg only has a ß-galactosidase activity, not a
permease activity, so the experimental system had to rely on the
pre-existing lac permease. Since the lac operon is
repressed in the absence of either allolactose or IPTG, Hall decided
to include the artificial inducer in all media up to this point so
that the cells could grow. Thus the system was being artificially
supported by intelligent intervention. Hall clearly wrote:
At this point it is important to discuss the use of IPTG in
these studies. Unless otherwise indicated, IPTG is always included
in media containing lactose or other ß-galactoside sugars. The sole
function of the IPTG is to induce synthesis of the lactose permease,
and thus to deliver lactose to the inside of the cell. Neither the
constitutive nor the inducible evolved strains grew on lactose in
the absence of IPTG. (Hall 1982b)
With further growth and
selection, Hall isolated secondary mutants with improved
ß-galactosidase activity. These mutants all had the same two changes
(mentioned above) at positions 92 and 977 of ebg
ß-galactosidase. Hall discovered that, in addition to hydrolyzing
lactose, the double mutants could also synthesize some allolactose,
just as the homologous lac ß-galactosidase can do, allowing
them to induce expression of the lac operon without further
need of IPTG. Critically again, however, the lac permease
induced by the action of the double mutant ebg is a
pre-existing protein, part of the original lac operon, and
was not produced in the experiment by the selection procedures. In
the absence of that required component, the bacteria cannot use
lactose.
Miller’s prose (“Irreducible complexity. What good
would the permease be without the galactosidase?”) (Miller 1999,
146) obscures the facts that most of the system was already in place
when the experiments began, that the system was carried through
nonviable states by inclusion of IPTG, and that the system will not
function without pre-existing components. In contrast to Miller,
Hall himself is cautious and clear about the implications of his
results.
The mutations described above have been
deliberately selected in the laboratory as a model for the way
biochemical pathways might evolve so that they are appropriately
organized with respect to both the cell and its environment. It is
reasonable to ask whether this model might have any relationship to
the real world outside the laboratory. If it is assumed that the
selection is strictly for lactose utilization, then a growth
advantage exists only when all three mutations are present
simultaneously. (Hall 1982a)
Hall is nonetheless optimistic.
Any one of the mutations alone could well be neutral (it is
unlikely that any would be disadvantageous); but neutral mutations
do enter populations by random chance events, and are fixed by a
chance process termed genetic drift. (Hall 1982a)
However,
if a mutation is not selected, the probability of its being fixed in
a population is independent of the probability of the next mutation.
Such a system is irreducibly complex, requiring several steps to be
taken independently of each other before having selective value. If
three mutations are required before there is any selective value,
then the cumulative probability starts to become very small indeed,
even considering the size of bacterial populations. In the present
case Hall argued that a small selective value might accrue after the
second mutation (in the ebg repressor). (Hall 1982a) However,
I find his rationale unconvincing and having little experimental
support. Furthermore, Professor Hall does not discuss the
implications of the requirement for the preexisting lac
permease gene.
Conclusion
Miller ends the
section in his typical emphatic style1:
No doubt about
it—the evolution of biochemical systems, even complex multipart
ones, is explicable in terms of evolution. Behe is wrong. (Miller
1999, 147)
I disagree. Leaving aside the still-murky area of
adaptive mutation, the admirably-careful work of Hall involved a
series of micromutations stitched together by intelligent
intervention. He showed that the activity of a deleted enzyme could
be replaced only by mutations to a second, homologous protein with a
nearly-identical active site; and only if the second repressor
already bound lactose; and only if the system were also artificially
supported by inclusion of IPTG; and only if the system were also
allowed to use a preexisting permease. Such results are exactly what
one expects of irreducible complexity requiring intelligent
intervention, and of limited capabilities for Darwinian processes.
References
Cairns, J. (1998). Mutation and
cancer: the antecedents to our studies of adaptive mutation.
Genetics 148, 1433-1440.
Foster, P. L. (1999).
Mechanisms of stationary phase mutation: a decade of adaptive
mutation. Annual Review of Genetics 33, 57-88.
Hall,
B. G. (1982a). Evolution of a regulated operon in the laboratory.
Genetics 101, 335-344.
Hall, B. G. (1982b). Evolution
on a Petri dish: The evolved ? ß-galactosidase system as a model for
studying acquisitive evolution in the laboratory. In Evolutionary
Biology. (M. K. Hecht, B. Wallace, and G. T. Prance, Eds.) pp.
85-150. (Plenum Press: New York.)
Hall, B. G. (1997). On the
specificity of adaptive mutations. Genetics 145, 39-44.
Hall, B. G. (1998). Adaptive mutagenesis: a process that
generates almost exclusively beneficial mutations. Genetics
102-103, 109-125.
Hall, B. G. (1999). Experimental evolution
of ebg enzyme provides clues about the evolution of catalysis
and to evolutionary potential. FEMS Microbiology Letters 174,
1-8.
McFadden, J. and Al Khalili, J. (1999). A quantum
mechanical model of adaptive mutation. Biosystems 50,
203-211.
Miller, K. R. (1999). Finding Darwin’s God: a
scientist’s search for common ground between God and evolution.
(Cliff Street Books: New York.)
Shapiro, J. A. (1997).
Genome organization, natural genetic engineering and adaptive
mutation. Trends in Genetics 13, 98-104.
Endnote
1. Miller’s prose is often
exaggerated and sometimes borders on the bombastic. Perhaps he uses
such a relentlessly emphatic style in the hope of overwhelming
readers through the sheer force of his words. Perhaps he just has a
much-larger-than-average share of self-confidence. Fortunately, in
this section on the “acid test,” experiments exist to show that his
prose is bluster. Let me be blunt—Miller always writes (or speaks)
with the utmost confidence, even when experiments show him to be
quite wrong. I would caution readers of his work not to be swayed by
his tone, whose confidence never wavers even when the evidence does.
Home | Feedback | Links | Books | Donate
| Back to Top
© 2024 TrueOrigin Archive. All Rights Reserved.
powered by Webhandlung